首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
相似文献
 共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 31 毫秒
1.
The present investigation is part of a program aimed at examining the mathematical basis of reaction rate theory (Bartholomay,Bull. Math. Biophys. 20, 1958) from the point of view of individual molecular events. Certain inconsistencies resulting from the classical procedure of using stoichiometric “chemical equations” to represent the kinds of mechanisms involved are pointed out and remedies are suggested by the introduction of set-theoretic notation within the framework of a so-calledMolecular Set Theory. It is concluded that whereas ordinary algebra is a suitable basis for stoichiometry, in discussing mechanisms of chemical reactions,molecular set theory is more appropriate. This is a theory of material transformations which is patterned afterabstract set theory: the individual molecules of a chemical species and chemical transformations from one species to another correspond to the abstract concepts of elements or points of a set and their mappings into other sets respectively. The new notions ofexact molecular sequences andequivalence classes of molecules arising from this study of chemical reactions may be of purely mathematical interest when referred back to the context of abstract set theory.  相似文献   

2.
After giving a brief review of the theory of organismic sets (Bull. Math. Biophysics,29, 139–152, 1967;31, 159–198, 1969), in which the concept of relational forces, introduced earlier (Bull. Math. Biophysics,28, 283–308, 1966a) plays a fundamental role, the author discusses examples of possible different structures produced by relational forces. For biological organisms the different structures found theoretically are in general agreement with observation. For societies, which are also organismic sets as discussed in the above references, the structures can be described only in an abstract space, the nature of which is discussed. Different isomorphisms between anatomical structures, as described in ordinary Euclidean space, and the sociological structures described in an abstract space are noted, as should be expected from the theory of organismic sets.  相似文献   

3.
A mathematical framework for a rigorous theory of general systems is constructed, using the notions of the theory of Categories and Functors introduced by Eilenberg and MacLane (1945,Trans. Am. Math. Soc.,58, 231–94). A short discussion of the basic ideas is given, and their possible application to the theory of biological systems is discussed. On the basis of these considerations, a number of results are proved, including the possibility of selecting a unique representative (a “canonical form”) from a family of mathematical objects, all of which represent the same system. As an example, the representation of the neural net and the finite automaton is constructed in terms of our general theory.  相似文献   

4.
A previous study (Bull. Math. Biophysics,31, 417–427, 1969) on the definitions of stability of equilibria in organismic sets determined byQ relations is continued. An attempt is made to bring this definition into a form as similar as possible to that used in physical systems determined byF-relations. With examples taken from physics, biology and sociology, it is shown that a definition of equilibria forQ-relational systems similar to the definitions used in physics can be obtained, provided the concept of stable or unstable structures of a system determined byQ-relations is considered in a probabilistic manner. This offers an illustration of “fuzzy categories,” a notion introduced by I. Bąianu and M. Marinescu (Bull. Math. Biophysics,30, 625–635, 1968), in their paper on organismic supercategories, which is designed to provide a mathematical formalism for Rashevsky's theory of Organismic Sets (Bull. Math. Biophysics,29, 389–393, 1967;30, 163–174, 1968;31, 159–198, 1969). A suggestion is made for a method of mapping the abstract discrete space ofQ-relations on a continuum of variables ofF-relations. Problems of polymorphism and metamorphosis, both in biological and social organisms, are discussed in the light of the theory.  相似文献   

5.
The theory of organismic sets, introduced by N. Rashevsky (Bulletin of Mathematical Biophysics,29, 139–152, 1967;30, 163–174, 1968), is developed further. As has been pointed out, a society is a set of individuals plus the products of their activities, which result in their interactions. A multicellular organism is a set of cells plus the products of their activities, while a unicellular organism is a set of genes plus the products of their activities. It is now pointed out that a physical system is a set of elementary particles plus the product of their activities, such as transitions from one energy level to another. Therefore physical, biological and sociological phenomena can be considered from a unified set-theoretical point of view. The notion of a “world set” is introduced. It consists of the union of physical and of organismic sets. In physical sets the formation of different structure is governed preponderantly by analytical functions, which are special type of relations. In organismic sets, which represent biological organisms and societies, the formation of various structures is governed preponderantly by requirements that some relations, which are not functions, be satisfied. This is called the postulate of relational forces. Inasmuch as every function is a relation (F-relation) but not every relation is a function (Q-relation), it has been shown previously (Rashevsky,Bulletin of Mathematical Biophysics,29, 643–648, 1967) that the physical forces are only a special kind of relational force and that, therefore, the postulate of relational forces applies equally to physics, biology and sociology. By developing the earlier theory of organismic sets, we deduce the following conclusions: 1) A cell in which the genes are completely specialized, as is implied by the “one gene—one enzyme” principle, cannot be formed spontaneously. 2) By introducing the notion of organismic sets of different orders so that the elements of an organismic set of ordern are themselves organismic sets of order (n−1), we prove that in multicellular organisms no cell can be specialized completely; it performs, in addition to its special functions, also a number of others performed by other cells. 3) A differentiated multicellular organism cannot form spontaneously. It can only develop from simpler, less differentiated organisms. The same holds about societies. Highly specialized contemporary societies cannot appear spontaneously; they gradually develop from primitive, non-specialized societies. 4) In a multicellular organism a specialization of a cell is practically irreversible. 5) Every organismic set of ordern>1, that is, a multicellular organism as well as a society, is mortal. Civilizations die, and others may come in their place. 6) Barring special inhibitory conditions, all organisms multiply. 7) In cells there must exist specially-regulatory genes besides the so-called structural genes. 8) In basically identically-built organisms, but which are built from different material (proteins), a substitution of a part of one organism for the homologous part of another impairs the normal functioning (protein specificity of different species). 9) Even unicellular organisms show sexual differentiation and polarization. 10) Symbiotic and parasitic phenomena are included in the theory of organismic sets. Finally some general speculations are made in regard to the possibility of discovering laws of physics by pure mathematical reasoning, something in which Einstein has expressed explicit faith. From the above theory, such a thing appears to be possible. Also the idea of Poincaré, that the laws of physics as we perceive them are largely due to our psychobiological structure, is discussed.  相似文献   

6.
The theory of relations between sets, proposed and outlined in previous publications (Bull. Math. Biophysics,23, 233–235, 1961;28, 117–124, 1966;28, 309–313, 1966), is tentatively expanded and generalized with a view to biological applications.  相似文献   

7.
The discussion as to whether societies are organisms andvice versa has been going on for a long time. The question is meaningless unless a clear definition of the term “organism” is made. Once such a definition is made, the question may be answered by studying whether there exists any relational isomorphism between what the biologist calls an organism and what the sociologist calls society. Such a study should also include animal societies studied by ecologists. Both human and animal societies are sets of individuals together with certain other objects which are the products of their activities. A multicellular organism is a set of cells together with some products of their activities. A cell itself may be regarded as a set of genes together with the products of their activities because every component of the cell is either directly or indirectly the result of the activities of the genes. Thus it is natural to define both biological and social organisms as special kinds of sets. A number of definitions are given in this paper which define what we call here organismic sets. Postulates are introduced which characterize such sets, and a number of conclusions are drawn. It is shown that an organismic set, as defined here, does represent some basic relational aspects of both biological organisms and societies. In particular a clarification and a sharpening of the Postulate of Relational Forces given previously (Bull. Math. Biophysics,28, 283–308, 1966) is presented. It is shown that from the basic definitions and postulates of the theory of organismic sets, it folows that only such elements of those sets will aggregate spontaneously, which are not completely “specialized” in the performance of only one activity. It is further shown that such “non-specialized” elements undergo a process of specialization, and as a result of it their spontaneous aggregation into organismic sets becomes impossible. This throws light on the problem of the origin of life on Earth and the present absence of the appearance of life by spontaneous generation. Some applications to problems of ontogenesis and philogenesis are made. Finally the relation between physics, biology, and sociology is discussed in the light of the theory of organismic sets.  相似文献   

8.
The field equation derived in Part I (Griffith,Bull. Math. Biophysics,25, 111–120, 1963a) is examined further. The stability of critical solutions is investigated and it is shown that, at least in certain cases, general solutions tend toward critical solutions. The relationship between the present field theory and a conventional matrix formulation is derived.  相似文献   

9.
In combining the author's theories of organismic sets (Rashevsky,Bull. Math. Biophysics,31, 159–198, 1969a) and Robert Rosen's theory of (M, R)-systems (Bull. Math. Biophysics,20, 245–265, 1958), a conclusion is reached that the number of either normal or pathological phenomena in organismic sets may occur. Those phenomena are characterized by occurring spontaneously once in a while but are not exactly periodic. Some epilepsies are an example of such pathological phenomena in the brain.  相似文献   

10.
In a previous paper (Bull. Math. Biophysics,22, 257–262, 1960), an expression for the probability that a car jumps off a road as a function of the speed and the size of the car was derived mostly from geometric and kinematic considerations, introducing only the reaction time as a biological parameter. In subsequent papers (Bull. Math. Biophysics,29, 181–186, 187–188, 1967) a more detailed study was made of the exact shape of the tracking curve of the car which involved several biological parameters of the driver. In the present paper the results of the previous studies are combined, and a more general equation for the probability of jumping off the road is obtained. This probability, as in the earlier study, increases with the speedv, widths o and lengthl o of the car, and decreases with widths of the lane. However, this probability also depends on several parameters which characterize the psychobiological constitution of the driver. Unpublished experiments by Ehrlich, which corroborate the general conclusions, are briefly described.  相似文献   

11.
This paper continues a comparison of the Taylor series and spherical harmonic forms of multipole representations initiated by Yeh (Bull. Math. Biophysics,24, 197–207, 1962). It is shown that while transformations from Taylor series form into spherical harmonic form is always possible, the inverse cannot be accomplished as suggested by Yeh; corrected transformation equations are given. It is also shown that direct measurement of Taylor coefficients, as outlined in Yeh, Martinek, and de Beaumont (Bull. Math. Biophysics,20, 203–216, 1958), is actually not possible. Accordingly, only the spherical harmonic coefficients can be determined by measurement of surface potentials, as in electrocardiography.  相似文献   

12.
In a previous paper (Bull. Math. Biophysics,12, 215, 1950) a theory of transmission of information through a chain of individuals was developed. It was assumed that each individual can exhibit only two mutually exclusive reactions, which serve as signals, thus transmitting to his neighbor one bit of information per signal. In the present paper the theory is generalized to the case of any numberm of mutually exclusive reactions, giving thus log2 m bits per signal. The general character of the process of transmission remains very much the same as before; the mathematical expression becoming, however, more complicated.  相似文献   

13.
The theory of organismic sets (Bull. Math. Biophysics,31, 159–189, 1969) is applied to the theory of leadership in human society. The ability of making decisions, required for leadership, is a product of the activities of the cells of the cerebral cortex, which are elements of the subsetS 02 of the organismic set “man” (loc. cit.). Products of the activities of the elements of an organismic set do not need to be of a material nature. Such things as thoughts, feelings, attitudes, etc., are also products of the activitiesa 1 of the elements. An individual can makeall necessary decisions for adaptation in a changing environment, when his subsetS 02 contains as a proper subset a set {a 12 ∼ ⊂S 02 of activities. It is shown that such individuals are rare. If none exist, then the one who possesses a subset {a 12 * ∼ ⊂ {a 12 ∼ of higher cardinalityc m than any other individual, will be the leader. The possibility is discussed that fromN individualsN′ 〈N possess subsets {a 12 * ∼ ⊂ {a 12 ∼ all of the same cardinalityc m but differing in the type of their elements, thus resulting in several leaders. It is then discussed what determines which of theNN′ individuals will choose a particular oneN′ individuals as leader. Cooperation and competition between leaders is discussed.  相似文献   

14.
In a series of papers, L. Danziger and G. Elmergreen (Bull. Math. Biophysics,16, 15–21, 1954;18, 1–13, 1956;19, 9–18, 1957) showed that a non-linear biochemical interaction between the anterior pituary gland and the thyroid gland may result under certain conditions in sustained periodical oscillations of the rates of production and of the blood level of the thyrotropic and of the thyroid hormone. They treated the systems, however, as a homogeneous one. N. Rashevsky (Some Medical Aspects of Mathematical Biology, Springfield, Illinois: Charles C. Thomas, Publisher, 1965;Bull. Math. Biophysics,29, 395–401, 1967) generalized the above results by taking into account the histological structures of the two glands as well as the diffusion coefficients and permeabilities of cells involved. The present paper is the first step toward the theory of interaction of any numbern of glands or, more generally,n components. The differential equations which govern the behavior of such a system represent a system of2n 2+n non-linear first order ordinary equations and involve a total of 7 n 2+3n parameters of partly histological, partly biochemical nature. The requirements of the existence of sustained oscillations demand 4n 2+2n+2 inequalities between those 7n 2+3n parameters.  相似文献   

15.
This paper, consisting of two parts, gives all the mathematical details that were omitted in a previous work by G. A. Sacher and E. Trucco (“The Stochastic Theory of Mortality.”Ann. N. Y. Acad. Sci.,96, 985–1007, cited here as ST). We assume that the reader is familiar with ST, where the stochastic theory of mortality, originally proposed by Sacher, is discussed at length. We recall that the basic model presented there refers to an ensemble of particles performing Brownian motion in one dimension, with the added constraint of two absorbing barriers. These two points, collectively, are designated as the “lethal bound.” Part I (section 1 to 4) deals with the special case in which the two absorbing barriers are symmetrically located at a finite distance from the origin. The solution of the Fokker-Planck equation is obtained from the theory of eigenvalue problems. Quite generally, the eigenfunctions functions belong to the family of Kummer's confluent hypergeometric functions, but the symmetry condition imposed here results in considerable simplification and makes it possible to estimate the first few eigenvalues by a graphical procedure. In section 3 we show how perturbation theory can be applied in the limiting case of “weak homeostasis,” and section 4 deals with the opposite extreme of “strong homeostasis.” A rigorous proof is given for the result corresponding to equation (28) of ST (asymptotic or quasi-static approximation for the “force of mortality”). This work was performed under the auspices of the U.S. Atomic Energy Commission.  相似文献   

16.
A previous study (Bull. Math. Biophysics,30, 735–749) is generalized to the case of active transport, which acts together in general with ordinary diffusion. The basic results obtained are the same except for an additional important conclusion. In principle it is possible to obtain sustained oscillations even when the secretions of the different glands do not affect the rates of formation or decay of each other at all, but affect the “molecular pumps,” which are responsible for the active transports in various parts of the system. Thus no biochemical interactions need necessarily take place between then-metabolites to make sustained oscillations possible in principle. This is an addition to a previous finding (Bull. Math. Biophysics,30, 751–760) that due to effects of the secreted hormones on target organs, non-linearity of biochemical interactions is not needed for production of sustained oscillations.  相似文献   

17.
We show that when we represent (ℓ, ℛ)-systems with fixed genome as automata (sequential machines), we get automata with output-dependent states. This yields a short proof that ((ℓ, ℛ)-systems from a subcategory of automata—and with more homomorphisms than previously exhibited. We show how ((ℓ, ℛ)-systems with variable genetic structure may be represented as automata and use this embedding to set up a larger subcategory of the category of automata. An analogy with dynamical systems is briefly discussed. This paper presents a formal exploration and extension of some of the ideas presented by Rosen (Bull. Math. Biophyss,26, 103–111, 1964;28, 141–148;28 149–151). We refer the reader to these papers, and references cited therein, for a discussion of the relevance of this material to relational biology.  相似文献   

18.
The general Theory of Categories is applied to the study of the (M, R)-systems previously defined. A set of axioms is provided which characterize “abstract (M, R)-systems”, defined in terms of the Theory of Categories. It is shown that the replication of the repair components of these systems may be accounted for in a natural way within this framework, thereby obviating the need for anad hoc postulation of a replication mechanism. A time-lag structure is introduced into these abstract (M, R)-systems. In order to apply this structure to a discussion of the “morphology” of these systems, it is necessary to make certain assumptions which relate the morphology to the time lags. By so doing, a system of abstract biology is in effect constructed. In particular, a formulation of a general Principle of Optimal Design is proposed for these systems. It is shown under what conditions the repair mechanism of the system will be localized into a spherical region, suggestive of the nuclear arrangements in cells. The possibility of placing an abstract (M, R)-system into optimal form in more than one way is then investigated, and a necessary and sufficient condition for this occurrence is obtained. Some further implications of the above assumptions are then discussed.  相似文献   

19.
The representation of biological systems in terms of organismic supercategories, introduced in previous papers (Bull. Math. Biophysics,30, 625–636;31, 59–70) is further discussed. To state more clearly this representation some new definitions are introduced. Also, some necessary changes in axiomatics are made. The conclusion is reached that any organismic supercategory has at least one superpushout, and this expresses the fact that biological systems are multistable. This way a connection between some results of Rashevsky’s theory of organismic sets and our results becomes obvious.  相似文献   

20.
A learning curve derived by H. D. Landahl (Bull. Math. Biophysics,3, 71–77, 1941) from postulated neurological structures is shown to be derivable from simplified assumptions by introducing the information measure of the uncertainty of response. The possible significance of this approach to learning theory is discussed.  相似文献   

设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号