共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 0 毫秒
1.
O'Malley MA Müller-Wille S 《Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences》2010,41(3):169-171
Although the cell is commonly addressed as the unit of life, historians and philosophers have devoted relatively little attention to this concept in comparison to other fundamental concepts of biology such as the gene or species. As a partial remedy to this neglect, we introduce the cell as a major point of connection between various disciplinary approaches, epistemic strategies, technological vectors and overarching biological processes such as metabolism, growth, reproduction and evolution. We suggest that the role of the cell as a nexus forms the basis for a new philosophical and historical appreciation of cell biology. This perspective focuses less on the cell as a well-defined, stable object and places more emphasis on its role as a mediator of fundamental biological processes. 相似文献
2.
Grmek MD 《History and philosophy of the life sciences》2001,23(1):5-12
The specific field of the history of science is the study and explanation of the origin and transformation of the structures of scientific knowledge. The historian of science should render understandable the reality of scientific research. The relationships between the history of science and the philosophy of science are examined stating that (1) the philosophical theories on the development of science have a scientific content only as much as they may be compared with the results of the history of science, and (2) the philosophy of science does not refer to an immediate historical reality but to an intellectual reconstruction of the past. 相似文献
3.
4.
There is a tension between science and philosophy, but this tension need not engender enmity or derision. Scientists and philosophers can work together, and we argue that working together is beneficial to both, even if it is sometimes uncomfortable. We offer examples of how philosophy can autonomously and effectively inform scientific practice. Science and philosophy share certain methodological concerns and practices; therefore, scientists who disregard philosophy are vulnerable to critical conceptual mistakes. If our arguments are correct, and if it can also be shown that science informs philosophy, then, while it is possible for both disciplines to operate autonomously, each should welcome the checks and balances that each provides for one another in the investigation and explanation of reality. 相似文献
5.
6.
Claessens M 《Médecine sciences : M/S》2011,27(8-9):777-780
In France, over 45 millions people watch TV every day for more than 3 hours. Science and image get well together since most TV watchers trust this media and rely on it (more than on any other source) for their scientific information. This emphasizes the power of images, which do not always deliver information, but can be naively regarded as creating communication. Image is necessary and an event which does not generate images is a non-event. Images are more than just a support for scientific messages: technologies have produced an enormous amount of images which allow us to uncover the mysteries of the world and Universe, their beauty and delicacy. We can be fascinated by the discovery of the invisible world which surrounds us, and science has truly generated artistic masterpieces even though we should remember that its primary goal is to understand the world rather than to create images. 相似文献
7.
8.
9.
10.
Netherlands Heart Journal - 相似文献
11.
A. Klug 《Philosophical transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B, Biological sciences》1997,352(1363):1763
Introduction to Ageing: science, medicine, and society, the proceedings of a Discussion held at The Royal Society on 7 and 8 May 1997. Organized and edited by J. Grimley Evans, R. Holliday, T. B. L. Kirkwood, P. Laslett and L. Tyler. 相似文献
12.
13.
Patricia A. Williams 《Biology & philosophy》1996,11(2):271-281
14.
15.
16.
17.
Summary This paper contains some considerations on the relation between philosophy of science and science, in particular biology. There is a contrast between formalistic and pragmatic approaches to the structure of scientific thought, which is illustrated by the different viewpoints on the nature of explanation. In an appendix some aspects of the logical structure of teleological explanation are discussed. 相似文献
18.
19.
20.
W. Ford Doolittle 《Biology & philosophy》2010,25(4):455-473
Lateral gene transfer (LGT), the exchange of genetic information between (primarily prokaryotic) lineages, not only makes
construction of a universal Tree of Life (TOL) difficult to achieve, but calls into question the utility and meaning of any
result. Here I review the science of prokaryotic LGT, the philosophy of the TOL as it figured in Darwin’s formulation of the
Theory of Evolution, and the politics of the current debate within the discipline over how threats to the TOL should be represented
outside it. We could encourage a more realistic and supportive public understanding of evolution by admitting that what we
believe in is not a unified meta-theory but a versatile and well-stocked explanatory toolkit. 相似文献